Theology Annual vol.16 1995 p.167-173
**********
Fr WONG in his article revisits the problem of the universal. He has recourse to Kant, not because Kant gave a satisfactory solution, but because his way of posing the question deserves further inquiry. After presenting a brief survey of solutions attempted by important philosophers from Kant back to Plato, the author states that the insight of Thomas Aquinas is still a reliable foundation on which to base the necessity and universality of metaphysical truth.
黃炎雄再探有關「普遍性」的問題。他引用康德,並非因為康德有一個滿意的答案,而是因為康德發問值得再反思。作者簡要地陳述一些哲學家們的立場,從康德推至柏拉圖,最後作者認為聖多瑪斯的見解,仍是可靠的路線,助人肯定到本體真理的「必然性」和「普遍性」。
**********
Copernicus
expressed his ingenious conviction about the revolution of the earth around
the sun in the form of plausible hypothesis; but the simplicity of his
formulation would not correspond to the radicality of the content.
It was one of those vigorous ideas, almost with one's own life, with
which one can be in agreement or in disconformity, but never indifferent.
In
the philosophical field, the Kantian revolution is like that not only because it
purports to be the inversion of the previous thought, but also because after the
Dissertatio of 1770, philosophers have not been able to stop
considering it and taking position before it.
In
contemporary philosophy, Kantism still leaves a sufficient mark, and its
consequences and influences are so important that we can affirm that in the
philosophical realm, we are still living in a Kantian atmosphere.
Nevertheless
the force of the philosopher of K
nigsberg is based on the depth and importance of the
questions which he asks than on the answers that he offers.
The problems he poses are truly basic topics.
How
are the sciences possible? With
this question, Kant initiated his investigation on the critical problem.
The question is highly interesting and Kant formulates it to perfection.
In the first place, it is perfectly legitimate, since it asks for the
foundation of the sciences. In the
second place, it is even obligatory for all the philosophers who are not
satisfied with describing what is given, but try to reach its explanation.
The
situation would be different if he asked whether the sciences were possible.
Doing that would incur in the clear illegitimacy of putting in doubt
the very existence of the sciences, which by itself is evident: "as these
sciences are really given, one can ask about them: how are they possible?
Since they have to be possible as it is demonstrated by their
reality"[1]
Kant
examines the constitutive elements of what he considers sciences in order to
isolate the essential ones from the accidental aspects.
These elements will make the sciences possible.
Before anything else, he observes that the scientific propositions
are always universal and necessary, or - with his words - synthetic a priori judgements.
For
the German philosopher, the constituted sciences are Mathematics and Physics;
but not Metaphysics. The motive of
this discrimination is the success of the former and the failure of the latter
in provoking the unanimous consent of those who profess them.
To elevate Metaphysics to the rank of the mentioned sciences is an
ethically praiseworthy try, although it is debatable insofar as its validity is
concerned. The previous question is
now posed in these words: Is Metaphysics possible as science?
It
is well-known that the historical knowledge of the philosopher of K
nigsberg is quite scarce.
It does not go beyond Leibnizian rationalism - impoverished and spread by
Wolff -, the empiricism of Hume and Newtonian physics.
This could make us think that the problems aroused by Kant are similar to
those which bothered Leibniz. The
comparison of both authors shows effectively that the Kantian doctrine is not
anything but a probing into the problems posed by his predecessor and an answer
to those questions which the latter has left open. For example, the Kantian question: "How are the sciences
(synthetic a priori judgements)
possible?" refers to the
Leibnizian problem: "How are the universal and necessary truths
possible?" Notwithstanding,
one particular point separates them: these truths belong, according to
Leibniz, as much to Mathematics, Physics, Metaphysics as to morals. Both authors have then a common concern: that of discovering
the foundation of Metaphysics. However,
in Leibniz the Kantian prejudice of not considering Metaphysics as science is
absent.
It
can be said, without fear of exaggeration, that the Kantian solution is the
consequence - certainly not wanted by its author - of the Leibnizian solution
brought to its extreme. Perhaps we
find ourselves before one of those sporadic cases in which the maxim enunciated
bravely by Kant is fulfilled: "Any philosopher understands his predecessors
better than they themselves". This
is reflected with particular clarity in determinate questions.
For
Professor Verneaux, in the question of the origin of knowledge, "Kant
follows Leibniz purely and simply. He
makes his own, under the new name of 'originating acquisition', the theory of
the virtual innatism of the ideas."[2]
A
scholar of Leibniz, Tonelli, suggests that "the Kantian revolution
took as one of its central characteristics the rejection of the sensibility as
the only source of knowledge. It is
then easy to infer that Kant's reading of the New
Essay Concerning Human Understanding (written by Leibniz) could be one of
the elements which pushed him to adopt his new solution"[3]
Entering
into the sphere of the probable that the reading of the New
Essays has contributed in a great way to waken up the dogmatic dream of the
creator of transcendental idealism, it can seem that this affirmation is
adventurous; but from the chronological point of view, it does not lack
foundation. Written in 1703-1705,
the New Essays were not published
until 1765, in the Raspe edition. The
philosophical works that appeared during the successive years after 1765 showed
that their authors did not understand with in depth the Leibnizian doctrine.
Only Kant understood if fully. And
the Dissertatio was given
birth in 1770. With this, one does
not pretend to affirm that Leibnizian innatism is Kant's only source of
influence. The innatism of Crusius
also plays an important role. Although
Kant did not accept at first moment this moderate innatism, the knowledge of
this doctrine could have called his attention by its analogy with that of
Leibniz. The combined influence of
both could be an important element in the famous philosophical revolution of
1770.[4]
The
questions formulated by Leibniz and Kant do not constitute an absolute novelty.
They are present in the previous philosophical systems; they were posed
already by Plato, four centuries before Christ, in this form: "Why the
universal and necessary truths are". A
question which for him gives rise to all intellectual development.
The
Platonic answer - the reminiscence - has great influence on the innate ideas of
Leibniz. According to the doctrine of the reminiscence, the
universal and necessary truths are in the soul in an unconscious way even
before its earthly existence. These
truths remain hidden until they become conscious in a determinate moment by a
series of perceptions which unleash in the soul an activity of comparison,
combination and conclusion. Therefore,
these truths are no more than remembrances of something forgotten, and their
universality and necessity are precisely founded on their independence from
experience.
St Augustine of Hippo, although influenced by Plato, could not accept the preexistence of the soul and rejects therefore the doctrine of the reminiscence, but he is aware of the fact that the sensible knowledge cannot give origin to the universal and necessary truths, because the object of the first ones are the changeable realities. The Bishop of Hippo proposes to us then his famous solution: the divine illumination. The soul finds or recognizes in itself the universal and necessary truths because God is its interior Master. More intimate to It than its own intimity, the soul consults with the immutable Truth the knowledge which it acquires, and in It, it finds the scientific truths. In the same way as the sun illuminates the corporeal things, God is the source of the spiritual light which makes the reason understand the scientific truths. If the sun is the source of light, God is the source of truth. It is important to take note that St Augustine has recourse to the divinity only to justify the universality and necessity of the truths, but not to obtain the content. He avoids in this way the danger of incurring in a material innatism, that is to say, an innatism of mental content.
This
question also called the attention of the Arab philosophers, among them,
Avicenna. Influenced by the neo-platonists and Greek commentators of
Aristotle, he affirmed - with a doctrine in conformity with that of Plato - that
the One, First Principle, creates the First Intelligence from which the
rest proceeds by successive emanations, the last one being a Separated Agent
Intellect common to all men. This
Agent Intellect is the dator formarum,
that is to say, the one who gives the form to the material beings and the
knowledge of them in men. In this
way, the universality and necessity of the truths are justified.[5]
In
the opposite direction, we find the Aristotelic - Thomistic thinkers, who grant
man the power which the Platonic line places outside of him.
It is enough for us to recall briefly here the position of St Thomas of
Aquinas who, following Aristotle, sustains that each man has his own agent
intellect. It corresponds to it to
justify the universality and necessity of the truths thanks to its capacity
to abstract - and therefore to educe - the essences of the things starting from
particular knowledge proceeding from the senses.
The
current of thought defending the existence of universal and necessary truths are
followed by Ockhamist nominalism which denies them stricto
sensu. Ockham centers his
attention in the particular beings, since for him there is no more reality than
the singular or individual, as experience attests it. Consequently, there is no general knowledge.
Nevertheless the experience itself seems to indicate that there are terms
which designate general concepts. Ockham
does not see in this more than the consequence of the limited human knowledge,
which does not distinguish various objects among themselves.
In principle, we should designate each thing or each real fact with a
different word, since a common
nature does not exist. In practice,
because of economy of words, we put a multitude of similar things or facts under
a same term; but being conscious of the fact that that "general" word
only has extension but no comprehension.
The nominalist doctrine was later on adopted in its fullness by the empiricists like Locke, Hume, etc. Locke, for example, was one of those who attacked most strongly the doctrine of innate ideas, above all in his work Essay Concerning Human Understanding.
As
a reaction against the empiricism of Locke, Leibniz wrote the Nouveaux
essais sur l'entendement humain answering point by point the Essay of the English. For
Leibniz, the existence of the universal and necessary truths is something
evident. In order to solve the question
of how they are possible, he has recourse to innatism because the truths in
question cannot come from the things themselves since experience only gives
us particular and contingent knowledge. Neither
does it seem to him plausible that there be a continuous divine illumination.
The Leibnizian solution, as he himself admits, is very much influenced by
Platonism, although he declares that he is not in total agreement with the
theory of the reminiscence.
Innatism,
as a solution to the critical problem, corresponds to the psychological point of
view. Nevertheless, we do not lack
the corresponding solution in a transcendental posture: the Kantian
apriorism.
The
doctrine of Kant sustains principally that transcendental knowledge or a priori knowledge is that which deals with objects in general,
different from the empirical objects, that is to say, that in which all the
objects - real or possible - converge and have to converge.
His thought is quite well-known and it is enough for our purpose to
remember that the matter of thought is the sensation, which gives us chaotic,
amorphous phenomena. These
phenomena are elaborated or ordered in two levels: first in the sensible level
by the a priori forms of this level (space and time); afterwards in the
intellectual level by the twelve categories, which are also a
priori forms. The universality
and the necessity of the knowledge are justified by the aprioristic forms, which
do not come from the experience. As
we can expect, the Kantian apriorism leads us to the conclusion that we only
know the thing-in-me but we do not know the thing-in-itself because the form is
given by the mind and it is not drawn from the thing in the reality.
Finally
comes Hegel who introduces the absolute idealism which denies totally the
existence of the external reality. For
him, the only real things are the ideas in the human mind.
The external reality is nothing more than a projection of the ideas in
our mind. In this way, he converts
the human mind into the creator of the things in the reality.
This
brief historical panorama indicates that the problem of the universal is
something perennial. The only
correct solution is the one which can maintain the proper connection between the
sense knowledge and the intellectual knowledge without falling into the
extremes.
The
nominalists and empiricists on one hand are correct in maintaining that the only
source of our knowledge is reality, our experience.
Nevertheless, they commit the error of stopping our knowledge in the
sensible level by denying the existence of universal truths.
The innatists and idealists on the other hand are correct in
distinguishing and accepting the jump between the sense knowledge and the
universal and necessary truths; however they fall into the mistake of driving a
wedge between them by claiming that the human mind is not a tabula
rasa but rather it has inborn knowledge which does not come from the senses.
From
here, we can see that the only correct solution to solve the critical question
(How are the universal and necessary truths possible?) is the Aristotelic
solution, maintained also by St Thomas of Aquinas, which affirms that each human
mind has the capacity to abstract from the sensible data the essences of things
in the reality; in this way, what we know is always the real nature of things in
the reality (the things-in-themselves, not the things-in-me) but at the same
time they do not remain in the particular level thanks to the power of the mind
to abstract, to leave behind the sensible and keep only the intelligible.
The Aristotelic-Thomistic solution is the only one which fulfills at the
same time two essential goals: maintaining the distance between sense knowledge
and the universal and necessary truths but without cutting the connection
between them. That distance is
important because thanks to it men are distinguished from the irrational beings,
and that connection is important because it is the only natural way by which the
truth of the universal and necessary knowledge can be saved.
As a conclusion we can say that the Aristotelic-Thomistic solution is the correct solution to the critical problem (the problem of the universal) because it is the solution which respects the true nature of man, a creature who does not only have a material body but also a spiritual soul; whereas the error of empiricism is to degrade man to the level of mere animal (i.e., without spiritual soul) and the mistake of idealism is to raise man to the level of God (i.e., forgetting his condition as a creature).
[1]KANT I., Cr tica de la razon pura, Vol.I, Trad. by MORENTE M.G. (Madrid: Liber a General de Victoriano Su rez 1928) 99.
[2]VERNEAUX R., Cr tica de la "Cr tica de la razon pura" (Madrid: Ed. Rialp 1978) 155.
[3]TONELLI G., Leibniz on Innate Ideas and the Early Reactions to the Publication of the Nouveaux Essais (1765) in J. Hist. Philoso 1974 (12) 437.
[4]Cf. Idem, 453.
[5]For more details, see HERNANDEZ M.C., Historia del pensamiento en el mundo isla mico, Vol.2 (Madrid: Ed. Alianza 1981) 193s..
網頁製作:聖神修院神哲學院